The Moral Architecture of a Whole-Nation State
Counterpart Assistance (Duìkǒu Zhīyuán) and the Cultural Continuity of Chinese Governance
Abstract
This article examines China’s duìkǒu zhīyuán (对口支援, counterpart assistance) system—an administrative mechanism that channels fiscal, technical, and human resources across regions during disasters, pandemics, and poverty-alleviation campaigns—as a moral technology of governance.
Rather than portraying it solely as bureaucratic mobilization within an authoritarian state, the paper situates counterpart assistance within a long civilizational genealogy that links modern mobilization to Confucian ethics of ren (benevolence), yi (righteousness), and he (harmony).
Through three case studies—the 2008 Wenchuan earthquake reconstruction, the 2020 Hubei “One Province–One City” COVID-19 response, and inter-provincial assistance and labor-transfer programs in Xinjiang—the paper argues that China’s administrative efficiency rests on a cultural logic of “self-healing collectivism.”
Drawing on comparative theorists from James C. Scott to Amartya Sen and Mary Douglas, it contrasts China’s moralized statecraft with liberal notions of autonomy and consent.
Ultimately, duìkǒu zhīyuán reveals how the Chinese state transforms compassion into coordination and virtue into infrastructure—challenging universalist assumptions about what it means for governance to be ethical.
Keywords: China, counterpart assistance, duìkǒu zhīyuán, Confucianism, moral governance, Wenchuan earthquake, COVID-19, Xinjiang, state mobilization, multiple modernities
1 Introduction
Observers of the People’s Republic of China routinely describe its crisis governance in terms of scale and efficiency.
Whether rebuilding after earthquakes or containing epidemics, China’s “whole-of-nation system” (jǔguó tǐzhì) appears to operate with mechanical precision: provinces adopt disaster zones, medical teams deploy overnight, and national logistics reconfigure as a single body.
Western commentary oscillates between admiration for administrative competence and alarm at centralized control.
Yet the analytical vocabulary—“authoritarian resilience,” “state capacity,” “command governance”—rarely engages with a deeper question: what moral imagination makes such mobilization legitimate and meaningful within China itself?
This article argues that duìkǒu zhīyuán is best understood as a moral architecture of the state.
It converts the Confucian obligation of mutual aid into bureaucratic form, sustaining collective action through ethical sentiment as much as through coercion.
2 Literature Review: Between Technocracy, Moral Order, and the Anthropology of the State
2.1 Authoritarian coordination or moral infrastructure?
Two interpretive lineages dominate studies of Chinese governance.
The first, institutionalist-technocratic, treats mobilization as a product of hierarchical coordination under authoritarian rule.Following the frameworks of fragmented authoritarianism (Mertha 2008) and state capacity (Fukuyama 2013), scholars such as Jessica Teets (2014) and Yuen Yuen Ang (2016) describe the “whole-of-nation system” as adaptive authoritarianism—flexible yet centrally commanded.
The second, emerging in Chinese scholarship and comparative political anthropology, conceives of these same mechanisms as moral infrastructures.Lu Xiaoli (2021) and Xu Hua (2019) trace a lineage from imperial 赈济 (relief) to socialist 支援 (aid), arguing that modern mobilization inherits the Confucian ethic of 协济 (mutual help).This view resonates with Fei Xiaotong’s From the Soil (1947), which portrays Chinese society as an “order of moral relationships” rather than legal contracts.
2.2 State rationality and the moral limits of modernity
Western theorists from Max Weber onward have wrestled with the moral vacuum of bureaucratic modernity.Weber (1922) described the modern state as an engine of rational-legal domination that “disenchants the world.”China’s governance complicates this model: it re-enchants bureaucracy by embedding virtue within it.
Mary Douglas (1970) showed that institutions embody symbolic classifications of purity and danger; Chinese bureaucracy sacralizes order itself.Alasdair MacIntyre (1981) lamented modernity’s loss of shared moral language; China’s retention of Confucian lexicon preserves precisely such a language.Michael Walzer (1983) distinguished “spheres of justice” across cultures; China’s redistribution via duìkǒu zhīyuán operates in a moral sphere of benevolence rather than contractual right.
James C. Scott (1998) warned against “high-modernist schemes” that produce “legibility without empathy.”Paradoxically, China’s pairing system is both hyper-legible and affectively charged—it transforms empathy into administrative order.
2.3 The moral economy of development and the anthropology of empathy
Amartya Sen (1999) defines development as freedom—the expansion of individual capabilities. China’s model inverts this premise: individuals gain freedom through integration into a moral-economic collective.This divergence reflects what Talal Asad (2003) terms the “genealogy of the secular”—the liberal West universalizing autonomy as the measure of humanity.
Anthropologists such as Clifford Geertz (1973) urge us to read policy as text. In China, the repeated invocation of brother provinces and hand-in-hand aid performs virtue linguistically; governance itself becomes moral storytelling. Work on the anthropology of the state (Ferguson and Gupta 2002; Das and Poole 2004) underscores that power operates through moral intimacy as well as coercion; duìkǒu zhīyuán exemplifies this intimacy on a national scale.
2.4 Community, imagination, and moral belonging
Benedict Anderson’s (1983) concept of “imagined community” remains central for analyzing how national belonging is narrated. China’s counterpart assistance constructs belonging through shared obligation rather than shared belief—the nation as moral household. Charles Taylor (1989) and MacIntyre (1998) locate virtue within communal narratives of the good; duìkǒu zhīyuán fits this communitarian frame, functioning as virtue ethics scaled to the nation.
2.5 Beyond dichotomies: plural modernities and the moral state
The theory of “multiple modernities” (Eisenstadt 2000) rejects the notion of a single Western path to rationality. China’s bureaucratic Confucianism illustrates a hybrid form—modern in technique, traditional in ethos. Daniel A. Bell (2006), Tu Weiming (2010), and Yan Yunxiang (2019) depict Confucian humanism as an alternative moral modernity that privileges relational duty over individual rights. Duìkǒu zhīyuán operationalizes what Bell calls “political meritocracy with moral purpose,” transforming benevolence into structural redistribution.
In sum, Western political theory separates power from virtue to limit authority; Chinese political culture fuses them to make power virtuous through responsibility. This synthesis—governance as ethics—frames the analysis that follows.
3 Theoretical Framework: Confucian Relational Ethics and the State as a Moral Body
To understand duìkǒu zhīyuán as more than a bureaucratic device, one must begin with the philosophical anthropology at the heart of Chinese political thought. Confucianism conceives of society not as an aggregation of autonomous individuals but as a network of morally charged relationships. Every tie—between ruler and subject, parent and child, elder and younger, teacher and student—carries ethical weight. Order arises not from law but from the right calibration of these relations, a state of dynamic equilibrium known as he (harmony). The moral person, or junzi, is not defined by private virtue alone but by the ability to sustain harmonious roles within this relational web.
The Confucian political cosmos therefore operates as an ethical continuum linking self, family, state, and the world. The famous dictum—“cultivate oneself, regulate the family, govern the state, bring peace to all under Heaven” (xiu qi zhi ping)—describes governance as the outward expansion of moral responsibility. It assumes that good government is not a matter of institutional checks but of moral resonance: the ruler’s virtue radiates downward, shaping the conduct of ministers, families, and communities. The ideal state is thus a moral body (da ti), an organism whose health depends on the proper flow of virtue through its limbs. The ruler’s benevolence acts as the heart’s pulse, animating society through moral circulation.
From this perspective, legitimacy arises not from consent but from moral exemplarity. Authority must persuade emotionally as well as command administratively. Ren (benevolence) represents the state’s inner sentiment of care; li (propriety) represents the external discipline through which that care is expressed. Together they form the dual code of governance: compassion institutionalized through ritual, feeling disciplined through form. When the two are aligned, the state becomes both efficient and humane; when they diverge, tyranny or chaos follows.
Within such a cosmology, social disorder or natural disaster signifies not only material crisis but moral disequilibrium. Earthquakes, epidemics, or widespread poverty are interpreted as symptoms of imbalance between Heaven, Earth, and humanity. Restoring order therefore requires the activation of empathy at scale—a renewal of the moral bonds that bind ruler and people, rich and poor, center and periphery. Confucian governance treats collective emotion as a resource: compassion, properly guided, is a force of restoration. In imperial China, this logic justified state-led relief campaigns and famine granaries, where the ruler’s generosity confirmed his Heaven-granted mandate. The same logic, modernized, animates contemporary mobilizations such as duìkǒu zhīyuán.
In this sense, duìkǒu zhīyuán can be seen as a modern moral technology, transforming the metaphysics of relational care into bureaucratic architecture. It operationalizes ren through fiscal transfers and cadre dispatch, and li through standardized procedures and performance metrics. Every element of the system—the pairing of provinces, the symbolic language of “brotherhood,” the ritualized ceremonies of deployment—translates ethical principles into administrative routines. What for Confucius was personal self-cultivation becomes, in the age of the modern state, institutional self-cultivation.
This moralization of bureaucracy differentiates Chinese statecraft from the value-neutral rationality envisioned by Max Weber. Where Weber’s “iron cage” of efficiency detaches means from ends, the Confucian state insists that means must embody moral ends. Bureaucratic competence without virtue is viewed as dangerous; virtue without structure, impotent. The state must therefore feel and act simultaneously—an empathy with command. In the idiom of contemporary governance, duìkǒu zhīyuán is the mechanism through which compassion is rendered legible to the state, budgeted, audited, and deployed.
The relational logic also explains why the Chinese state often speaks the language of family. The metaphor of “motherland” (zuguo) and “brother provinces” is not rhetorical ornament but the natural extension of familial ethics into public life. Just as a parent’s responsibility legitimizes authority within the home, the state’s paternal benevolence legitimizes its authority over citizens. This familial model does not abolish hierarchy but seeks to humanize it, replacing impersonal law with mutual care. Duìkǒu zhīyuán institutionalizes this paternal ethos: it transforms the family’s moral impulse—to assist one’s kin in distress—into a nationwide governance strategy.
Critically, this relational morality reframes the notion of participation. In liberal political culture, moral virtue is expressed through individual choice; in Confucian political culture, it is realized through relational duty. Citizens demonstrate virtue not by asserting autonomy but by fulfilling obligations to the collective. When mobilizations such as post-disaster reconstruction or pandemic aid occur, the moral question is not whether individuals consent but whether they respond. The emphasis lies on resonance rather than resistance, harmony rather than contract.
The result is a political culture that values empathic governance—a state that must constantly demonstrate its capacity to feel the people’s suffering and to respond in kind. The language of “the Party shares the people’s heart” or “the nation breathes as one” is not mere propaganda; it is the expression of a cosmology where moral vibration ensures legitimacy. When compassion falters, dynasties fall; when empathy is institutionalized, the polity endures.
Thus, modern duìkǒu zhīyuán represents both continuity and transformation. It inherits the Confucian conviction that governance is an ethical art and adapts it to the bureaucratic scale of the modern nation-state. It aligns compassion with command, ritual with regulation, and moral feeling with fiscal capacity. In doing so, it sustains an alternative vision of modernity—one in which the state remains not a machine but a moral body, and empathy, rather than law alone, remains the ultimate measure of order.
4 Case Study I: Wenchuan Earthquake (2008)
When a magnitude 8.0 earthquake struck Sichuan on 12 May 2008, killing nearly 90,000 people and leveling entire towns, China’s political system responded with a speed and scale that startled even seasoned observers. Within weeks, Beijing unveiled a national plan that assigned nineteen provincial-level administrations—including Shanghai, Beijing, Guangdong, and Jiangsu—to take direct responsibility for rebuilding eighteen of the worst-hit counties and cities. Each supporting province pledged roughly one percent of its annual fiscal revenue and dispatched teams of engineers, planners, teachers, doctors, and civil servants to live and work in the disaster zone for at least three years. These were not temporary relief missions; they were sustained partnerships formalized through contracts, performance indicators, and a shared ethos of duty.
What distinguished this massive mobilization was not only its logistical precision but also its moral narrative. Official discourse described the arrangement in familial terms: “brother provinces,” “hand-in-hand reconstruction,” “a nationwide family rebuilding its home together.” The campaign’s rhetoric drew deeply on Confucian notions of xieji zhidao (协济之道)—the Way of mutual aid—where helping the afflicted is not charity but reciprocity within a moral organism. Each province became an elder sibling assuming responsibility for its wounded kin. In state media and public imagination alike, the boundary between donor and recipient blurred: Sichuan’s suffering was rendered as the nation’s suffering, and reconstruction as collective redemption.
On the ground, this moral grammar manifested in concrete acts of coordination. Shanghai’s planners rebuilt Dujiangyan’s schools and hospitals with the same architectural aesthetics used along the Huangpu River, symbolically transplanting metropolitan modernity into the mountain valleys. Beijing oversaw the reconstruction of Shifang, embedding its own municipal standards into local governance. Guangdong, wealthier and more industrialized, assumed the task of rebuilding Wenchuan County itself, its engineers working side by side with local laborers to raise bridges and waterworks from rubble. Across the province-pairings, provincial cadres lodged in temporary barracks, often in the same dormitories as local officials, creating what participants later called “shared hardship and shared rebirth.”
The program’s governance design combined central command with decentralized execution. The National Development and Reform Commission coordinated funds and targets, but each paired province enjoyed relative autonomy in deciding local projects. This hybrid model of trust and hierarchy reflected a long-standing Chinese administrative philosophy: the center articulates moral vision, the localities embody it through practical action. Moral sentiment and managerial rationality thus reinforced each other—the very fusion that underpins duìkǒu zhīyuán as a moral technology.
Equally important was the emotional mobilization of society. Millions donated through state-sanctioned charity drives; students and retired workers volunteered in rebuilding efforts; national television broadcast stories of “relatives from afar” arriving to help “brothers and sisters in Sichuan.” The collective empathy was palpable and performative: public mourning on 19 May 2008—three minutes of nationwide silence—became a ritual of solidarity. In those moments, the moral unity of the nation felt not imposed but experienced, an affective infrastructure binding bureaucratic coordination with civic feeling.
By 2010, over 90 percent of the planned reconstruction projects had been completed: more than 3 million homes rebuilt, 3,000 schools reopened, and transportation networks restored or expanded. The affected areas not only recovered but in many cases surpassed pre-quake economic output, a rare outcome in global disaster recovery. The “Wenchuan model” quickly entered the policy lexicon as evidence that empathy, when institutionalized, could be efficient; that compassion, when orchestrated, could rival capital as a source of productivity. International agencies such as the World Bank and the Global Facility for Disaster Reduction and Recovery cited it as an unprecedented case of “whole-of-nation” post-disaster governance.
Yet the moral triumph carried contradictions. The emotional unity that empowered rapid reconstruction also suppressed debate about long-term sustainability, debt burdens, and local autonomy. Some scholars noted that local residents, grateful yet dependent, felt hesitant to question design decisions imposed by outside experts. Others observed that the architectural uniformity of new towns symbolized not just recovery but assimilation—an imprint of the supporting provinces’ identity on local landscapes. In this sense, duìkǒu zhīyuán in Wenchuan embodied the paradox of organized benevolence: compassion delivered through hierarchy, solidarity expressed through control.
Still, within China’s collective memory, the earthquake became a moral watershed. It confirmed the belief that national unity was not merely political but ethical—that the state could act as the conscience of society. Annual commemorations emphasize not tragedy but fraternity: the notion that out of destruction arose proof of the nation’s moral vitality. The Wenchuan experience thus crystallized the cultural DNA of later mobilizations, from poverty alleviation campaigns to pandemic responses. It offered a blueprint for how empathy could be designed, scaled, and managed—a demonstration that in the Chinese imagination, virtue need not stand apart from power, and that the hand which commands can also be the hand that cares.
5 Case Study II: COVID-19 and the Hubei Pairing Mechanism (2020)
When the COVID-19 outbreak began to overwhelm Wuhan and Hubei Province in early 2020, China responded with a mobilization whose scale and moral symbolism rivaled its disaster reconstruction campaigns. Within days of the central government’s declaration of a “public health emergency of the highest level,” an unprecedented pairing system was launched: every Chinese province, autonomous region, and major municipality was assigned to support one prefecture-level city in Hubei. This “One Province–One City” arrangement transformed the entire country into an organism of mutual aid, a living network of care that mirrored the earlier Wenchuan model but with medicine rather than construction as its medium.
Under this plan, more than 42,000 doctors, nurses, and public health workers were deployed to Hubei from across China. The assignments were precise—Jiangsu paired with Jingzhou, Zhejiang with Xiaogan, Guangdong with Xianning, and so on. Each team arrived with its own logistical unit, medical supplies, and chain of command, creating temporary mirror-images of their home institutions inside Hubei’s hospitals. The initiative represented not only administrative agility but a moral choreography: an act of national empathy rendered in spreadsheets and convoys. Provinces were not merely providing assistance; they were symbolically embracing their counterparts, binding local identities to a shared fate.
For those who volunteered, the decision to join was both deeply personal and socially inevitable. Chinese media celebrated the doctors as nìxíngzhě (逆行者)—“those who walk against the tide.” The term carried moral resonance: to move toward danger when others retreat is the highest form of ren, the Confucian virtue of benevolence. Participation thus combined voluntarism with moral inevitability. While no one was formally coerced, the social expectation of self-sacrifice was palpable. To decline an assignment would have been perceived not simply as professional hesitation but as a failure of moral character—a refusal to embody the unity that defines virtue in Chinese civic culture. In this sense, ren became policy, and compassion was no longer an individual emotion but a collective mandate.
The emotional intensity of the mobilization was reinforced by ritualized communication. National television broadcast daily footage of convoys departing from distant cities under banners reading “Go Wuhan! The nation stands with you!” Local governments organized farewell ceremonies where medical workers pledged oaths beneath national flags. Citizens watching from their homes wept as they sang the national anthem, reinterpreting a crisis of biology as a drama of belonging. Such scenes, carefully curated but widely sincere, transformed bureaucratic coordination into moral theatre. They also provided the affective glue that made compliance effortless: when duty and empathy converge, obedience feels like devotion.
Inside Hubei’s hospitals, the pairing system created hybrid institutions. Doctors from Shanghai, for example, managed intensive-care wards in Wuhan using the same protocols as in their home hospitals, effectively replicating metropolitan expertise in the epicenter of the crisis. These imported teams not only supplied labor and technology but also reconstituted the moral rhythm of the institutions they supported. The daily rituals of collective meals, team photos, and inter-provincial camaraderie reinforced the sense that the nation itself was tending to the sick. This moral personalization of state capacity distinguished China’s pandemic governance from the technocratic minimalism of many Western systems. The objective was not merely to treat patients but to embody compassion through administration.
At the level of governance, the pairing mechanism reflected a sophisticated synthesis of centralization and delegation. The National Health Commission and the Central Leading Group on COVID-19 provided directives, but implementation rested with provincial teams whose internal hierarchies mirrored their home bureaucracies. The system thus achieved both uniformity and flexibility: a single ethical command—save lives, protect Hubei—translated into thousands of localized actions. This design echoed the Confucian statecraft principle of “central morality, local enactment” (德出于上,行成于下), whereby virtue flows downward and finds its expression in concrete care.
For many Chinese citizens, the moral experience of the pandemic was defined by this visible solidarity. The pairing of provinces and cities gave abstract national unity a tangible form; it made compassion legible on the map. People could trace empathy geographically: Shanghai was caring for Wuhan, Guangdong for Xianning, and so forth. Such visualization transformed the epidemic from a catastrophe into a collective moral exercise—a test of whether China could act as one family. The outcome, measured both in epidemiological control and in emotional resonance, reinforced the conviction that unity itself is a form of benevolence.
Western observers were sharply divided in their interpretations. Some praised China’s extraordinary state capacity, reading the One Province–One City strategy as a model of logistical efficiency and decisive governance. Others viewed it as the apotheosis of coercive collectivism, a reminder that in an authoritarian system, altruism can never be disentangled from command. Both assessments, however, miss the internal moral logic that makes such mobilization intelligible within China. From a Confucian perspective, unity is not the enemy of compassion but its precondition: only a harmonized society can feel fully, just as only a healthy body can heal its limbs. The mobilization therefore expressed what might be termed bureaucratized benevolence—an administrative system animated by moral emotion, where empathy and hierarchy reinforce rather than contradict each other.
Yet this very moralization also reveals the model’s ambiguities. The exaltation of sacrifice can blur the line between heroism and expectation; the celebration of unity can render dissent emotionally illegitimate. Doctors who questioned safety conditions or resource shortages risked appearing ungrateful, even disloyal. Within the moral grammar of the campaign, criticism sounded like coldness. Such tensions expose the double edge of duìkǒu zhīyuán: its capacity to humanize bureaucracy is matched by its tendency to moralize compliance. Still, for many participants, the experience was transformative. The pandemic became not only a crisis of health but a reaffirmation of collective empathy—a reminder that the moral identity of the Chinese state rests on its ability to act, and feel, as one.
By the time Hubei reopened in April 2020, the pairing system had become both a logistical success and a national myth. It demonstrated that China’s political culture could turn compassion into command and command back into compassion, creating a virtuous cycle of legitimacy. The One Province–One City mechanism thus stands as the most vivid contemporary example of duìkǒu zhīyuán as moral technology: empathy scaled to governance, unity performed as care, and benevolence bureaucratized without apology.
6 Case Study III: Xinjiang and Labor-Transfer Poverty Alleviation
In China’s far west, the idea of duìkǒu zhīyuán has taken on a distinctly political and moral significance. Since 2013, as part of the national Targeted Poverty Alleviation campaign, the central government expanded the long-standing “Pairing Aid to Xinjiang” (yuàn jiāng) program, linking prosperous coastal provinces such as Guangdong, Zhejiang, and Shandong with prefectures in southern Xinjiang like Kashgar, Hotan, and Aksu. These partnerships were designed not only to transfer funds and technology but to build roads, schools, and industrial zones capable of absorbing surplus rural labor. Each supporting province sent cadres and technical specialists to co-manage local development, making duìkǒu zhīyuán an experiment in cross-regional social engineering—one that sought to fuse moral obligation, political integration, and economic modernization.
Officially, these initiatives were framed as a campaign to “teach a man to fish rather than give him a fish.” The slogan carried an unmistakable Confucian undertone: self-reliance as virtue, diligence as moral rehabilitation. It also echoed Marxist labor ethics, which define productive work as both the foundation of personal dignity and the path to collective emancipation. Within China’s domestic discourse, poverty was not merely an economic condition but a moral one—an imbalance between effort and opportunity that could be corrected through guided participation in labor. Thus, the state’s role was pedagogical as much as material: to create the conditions under which individuals could cultivate themselves through work.
In practice, the “labor-transfer” component of this model involved organizing rural residents—particularly from minority communities in southern Xinjiang—to take jobs in newly built industrial parks or, in some cases, to migrate to factories in other provinces. Provincial pairing partners funded vocational training centers, subsidized transport, and offered incentives to enterprises that hired Xinjiang workers. For Beijing, these measures embodied what it called “employment-centered poverty alleviation,” transforming welfare dependency into moral agency. The ideal outcome was what official documents termed “two transformations”: from peasant to worker, and from passive recipient to active contributor.
At the ideological level, this program merged two ethical languages: Marxist emancipation through labor and Confucian self-cultivation through effort. Both posit that virtue is realized not through autonomy in the liberal sense but through the fulfillment of socially meaningful roles. In this worldview, labor is not exploitation but moral practice—the means by which one harmonizes self and society. The enterprise zone or workshop thus functions not only as a site of production but as a classroom of modernity, a space where citizens are remade into moral subjects.
However, outside China this moral vocabulary is largely unintelligible. Western NGOs and human-rights organizations interpret the same policies through the lens of autonomy and consent, where moral legitimacy depends on individual choice. From this perspective, any organized transfer of labor that involves state coordination, ideological instruction, or pressure to relocate constitutes coercion. Reports from groups such as Human Rights Watch, Amnesty International, and the Australian Strategic Policy Institute frame these initiatives as evidence of systemic control—a continuation of securitization by economic means. In contrast, Chinese officials cite rising household incomes, infrastructure investment, and employment stability as proof that these programs embody benevolent governance.
The chasm between these interpretations reveals a deeper moral incommensurability. In the liberal imagination, freedom is the ground of virtue; in the Confucian imagination, virtue is the ground of freedom. Western observers assume that agency precedes obligation, while Chinese political culture assumes that obligation enables agency. These are not simply competing narratives but distinct ontologies of the self. One measures legitimacy by the individual’s capacity to refuse; the other, by the community’s capacity to care. Hence, debates over Xinjiang’s labor policies often devolve into moral monologues rather than dialogues: each side speaks a language the other cannot translate.
To understand how duìkǒu zhīyuán operates in Xinjiang, one must see it as both moral project and statecraft. For Beijing, aiding Xinjiang is a continuation of the centuries-old 协济之道—the obligation of the strong to support the weak, of the center to nurture the periphery. It also embodies the post-1949 socialist promise to erase regional inequality and ethnic marginalization through development. Under this logic, pairing Guangdong with Kashgar or Zhejiang with Hotan is more than economic planning; it is an ethical gesture of national integration, a performance of tianxia yi jia—“all under Heaven as one family.”
On the ground, the reality is complex and often contradictory. Many transferred workers report higher incomes and improved housing, yet they also experience cultural estrangement, strict workplace discipline, and limited bargaining power. For local cadres, success is measured less by worker satisfaction than by employment quotas and social stability targets, turning compassion into quantifiable metrics. The moral ideal of ren (benevolence) thus becomes intertwined with the political imperative of control. As in other forms of duìkǒu zhīyuán, empathy is bureaucratized: the duty to help acquires administrative deadlines, performance reviews, and audit trails.
Still, within China’s internal moral horizon, these contradictions are not seen as hypocrisy but as the price of collective harmony. To govern compassion is to discipline it; to make empathy effective, one must make it obedient. This conviction reflects a cultural confidence that moral ends justify institutional means, provided the intention remains benevolent. It also explains why Chinese officials often respond to Western criticism with incomprehension: from their standpoint, to question organized assistance is to question the very possibility of moral governance.
In this sense, counterpart assistance in Xinjiang becomes a mirror reflecting two civilizations’ definitions of what it means to help. For the liberal West, aid is legitimate only when chosen; for Confucian China, aid is meaningful only when shared. Each side fears what the other values: the West fears paternalism, China fears indifference. Between these poles lies the ethical paradox of duìkǒu zhīyuán: a project that seeks to humanize power through virtue, yet in doing so risks sanctifying authority itself. Xinjiang thus stands not only as a geopolitical flashpoint but as the deepest test of China’s moral statecraft—whether compassion can be organized without coercion, and whether duty can uplift without dominating.
7 Discussion: The Governance of Empathy
Empathy, in most political traditions, is considered a private virtue—an individual’s moral sentiment rather than an administrative principle.
What distinguishes China’s duìkǒu zhīyuán system is that it institutionalizes empathy: it transforms moral feeling into organizational design.
Disaster relief, epidemic response, and poverty alleviation become ritualized acts through which the state and its citizens perform benevolence together.
This fusion of morality and management—what might be called the governance of empathy—offers both the strength and the paradox of the Chinese model.
7.1 Empathy as structure, not sentiment
In the Confucian lexicon, ren (仁) signifies more than compassion; it is the capacity to perceive others as extensions of oneself.When the state invokes duìkǒu zhīyuán, it operationalizes this principle through a network of reciprocal obligations:each province paired with another, each cadre paired with a village, each medical team paired with a hospital.Empathy becomes measurable, reportable, and accountable—no longer a spontaneous act but a routinized duty.
This routinization does not necessarily hollow out moral meaning.Rather, it embeds virtue within administrative procedure.By assigning compassion a bureaucratic form, the Chinese state makes benevolence scalable; it turns what Aristotle called phronesis—practical wisdom—into gongzuo jihua—work plan.Such translation from virtue to policy is precisely what enables a population of 1.4 billion to act “as one family” in moments of crisis.
7.2 Bureaucratic ritual and moral participation
The pairing mechanism also functions as a civic ritual.During the Wenchuan reconstruction, banners declaring “Shanghai and Dujiangyan—One Heart” lined construction sites; during the COVID-19 outbreak, hospital corridors bore slogans like “Beijing and Wuhan fight side by side.”These performances are not trivial propaganda but acts of collective empathy.They visualize the moral proximity of strangers and transform bureaucratic assignments into narratives of kinship.
Anthropologically, such rituals reaffirm the Confucian belief that emotion (qing) and propriety (li) must co-govern social life.Empathy without order leads to chaos; order without empathy hardens into oppression.The genius—and risk—of duìkǒu zhīyuán lies in maintaining that balance: creating an empathetic state that is disciplined, yet emotionally resonant.
7.3 Moral obedience and the absence of visible coercion
Western theories of power often equate obedience with constraint.In the Chinese context, obedience can also signify belonging.Because duty is moralized, compliance carries the aura of virtue.When a doctor volunteers for Hubei or a county cadre relocates to an impoverished township, the act fulfills not an order but a calling.This sense of moral participation explains how large-scale mobilizations occur with limited enforcement: citizens act through xin tong gan tong—shared mind and feeling.
Yet the absence of visible coercion does not mean the absence of pressure.Moral expectations can compel as strongly as legal sanctions.The emotional economy of duìkǒu zhīyuán—praise for “heroes,” shaming of “slackers”—creates what Michel Foucault might call “disciplinary empathy,” where the individual internalizes the collective gaze.Still, this internalization differs from Western disciplinary power because it is couched in relational warmth rather than surveillance coldness; it constrains through care, not fear.
7.4 Empathy as state capacity
From a governance perspective, empathy serves as a form of social capital that reduces transaction costs.When trust is cultural rather than contractual, coordination accelerates.The paired-aid system builds dense moral networks that substitute for market or legal mechanisms of accountability.Officials from the aiding province stake their personal honor on the well-being of the recipient region, creating quasi-familial bonds of responsibility.
This relational trust complements, rather than replaces, bureaucratic rationality.The state’s ability to mobilize resources in days depends on both vertical command and horizontal empathy.In effect, China integrates Max Weber’s rational-legal order with what we might call a Confucian affective order—one that governs through moral resonance.Such synthesis helps explain why campaigns framed in moral terms—fupin gongjian (poverty alleviation partnership) or fangyi yizhi (epidemic prevention solidarity)—generate extraordinary compliance without the appearance of compulsion.
7.5 The double edge of organized benevolence
However, empathy’s institutionalization introduces its own pathologies.When compassion becomes compulsory, sincerity blurs into performance.Cadres compete to display devotion; citizens perform gratitude to avoid suspicion.The moral vocabulary of unity can delegitimize dissent: to question a campaign is to appear heartless.This is what Mary Douglas (1970) described as the “pollution of the sacred”—when moral order, made absolute, excludes the ambiguous and the critical.
Thus, the governance of empathy oscillates between ethical cohesion and moral overreach.Its success in producing obedience without repression risks substituting emotional conformity for deliberative participation.The very affect that binds society may inhibit contestation—the lifeblood of innovation and rights protection.
7.6 Comparative reflections: Empathy by law, empathy by virtue
Liberal bureaucracies, shaped by distrust of moral authority, rely on law and rights to mediate compassion.The welfare state distributes care impersonally through entitlement; empathy is abstracted into procedure.Citizens claim assistance as a right, not as a relationship.China’s model reverses this logic: care is distributed relationally through obligation; empathy is personal but hierarchical.Each approach embodies a distinct answer to the same question—how to translate feeling into fairness.
The liberal state seeks justice through equality before the law; the Confucian state seeks justice through appropriateness of relation.Where one says “every citizen is the same,” the other says “each citizen deserves what fits their place.”Neither formula guarantees virtue; both risk failure when empathy or legality becomes empty ritual.But their coexistence underscores the plurality of moral modernities.
7.7 Empathy as governing imagination
Ultimately, duìkǒu zhīyuán reveals a distinctive governing imagination—a belief that emotional cohesion can be engineered as effectively as economic growth.The state does not merely command behavior; it choreographs sentiment.In doing so, it redefines legitimacy: authority is measured not only by compliance rates but by the capacity to evoke tong qing (shared feeling). This re-emotionalization of governance challenges Western assumptions that modernity must mean affective neutrality.
Yet it also invites reflection on universality.If the liberal project seeks to humanize the state by constraining it, the Confucian project seeks to humanize it by moralizing it.Both are responses to the same human dilemma—how power can care without dominating.In China’s case, empathy becomes both the justification for centralized coordination and the cultural safeguard against its potential cruelty.
Across disasters, pandemics, and development drives, duìkǒu zhīyuán demonstrates the Chinese state’s capacity to institutionalize moral sentiment.It moralizes administration, producing participation that feels voluntary even when it is obligatory.
By embedding compassion in bureaucracy, the system achieves cohesion without constant coercion—but at the cost of narrowing the moral vocabulary available for critique.Where liberal states govern through law and rights, China governs through virtue and relation: a governance of empathy that aspires to make authority feel humane, and in that aspiration, reveals both the promise and the peril of moralized power.
8 Comparative Analysis: Two Moral Economies of Governance
8.1 Two historical traumas, two political reflexes
Every political tradition carries the memory of its founding trauma.For the modern West, that trauma was absolutism—the fear that unchecked virtue in the hands of rulers would mutate into tyranny.The Enlightenment’s solution was institutionalized distrust: separate morality from power, divide power against itself, and regulate rulers by law.John Locke’s Second Treatise replaced moral duty with consent; Jean-Jacques Rousseau’s social contract located sovereignty in collective will rather than moral charisma.When Tocqueville later warned that democracy might breed a “mild despotism,” he was extending this reflex of suspicion.Liberal governance therefore imagines safety as freedom from others’ virtue.
China’s formative trauma, by contrast, was disunity—the Warring States chaos and recurrent civil wars that threatened social dissolution.The Confucian remedy was institutionalized trust: cultivate virtue at every level of hierarchy so that power becomes morally self-limiting.Mencius’ dictum that “those who win the people’s hearts rule the empire” grounded legitimacy in benevolence rather than consent.Even the Legalist synthesis under Han Feizi did not erase this ethos; it disciplined virtue through law but never abandoned the belief that order requires moral exemplarity.Where liberalism fears moral authority, Chinese governance depends upon it.
These divergent starting points explain the inverse logic of their institutional designs.Liberalism treats checks and balances as the moralization of politics; Confucianism treats morality itself as the ultimate check.
8.2 The architecture of distrust vs. the architecture of trust
The liberal state secures virtue through impersonality.Its ideal bureaucracy is value-neutral, governed by procedure, and accountable through transparency.Michel Foucault (1978) traced this rationalization to the emergence of governmentality—a regime where populations are managed through statistics and surveillance rather than virtue.Within this paradigm, morality is privatized; the good citizen is law-abiding, not necessarily benevolent.
By contrast, the Confucian state secures virtue through personalization.Power is relational: ruler and subject, parent and child, cadre and citizen mirror one another’s moral standing.Daniel Bell (2006) calls this “political meritocracy”—an aspiration that officials should be not only competent but ren-xin (humane-hearted).Tu Weiming (2010) describes it as “self-cultivation as governance”: to govern others one must first govern oneself.Hence campaigns like duìkǒu zhīyuán can be read as exercises in collective self-cultivation, scaling the family ethic to the national level.
In the liberal architecture of distrust, virtue is dangerous because it justifies domination.In the Confucian architecture of trust, virtue is indispensable because it humanizes domination.Both systems guard against the pathology they fear most: the West fears the tyranny of virtue; China fears the anomie of virtue’s absence.
8.3 Freedom and unity as moral inversions
From these architectures emerge opposite formulas of moral security.For Western polities scarred by absolutism, freedom guarantees safety.Political freedom, civil rights, and pluralism are bulwarks against the moral ambitions of the state.As Isaiah Berlin’s “negative liberty” insists, the absence of coercion is itself the highest good.The liberal citizen must be protected from the benevolent despot no less than from the cruel one.
For China, whose historical anxiety is fragmentation, unity guarantees compassion.Order is the precondition for moral life: only within harmony can benevolence circulate.The Confucian tradition repeatedly warns that chaos (luan) erodes virtue; as Xunzi wrote, “Without rites, people cannot dwell together.”In modern terms, the state becomes the guarantor of relational trust. Hence large-scale mobilizations—from Wenchuan reconstruction to pandemic response—are framed not as suspensions of liberty but as enactments of collective care.
To Western observers, such mobilization seems coercive precisely because it demands moral participation rather than mere compliance.To Chinese participants, it feels moral precisely because it converts obedience into empathy.The difference is not empirical but ontological: two moral economies of order, one founded on the autonomy of conscience, the other on the reciprocity of roles.
8.4 Public morality and the scope of the self
Liberal ethics imagines the individual as the fundamental moral unit.Responsibility flows outward from self to society; social contracts aggregate private wills into public goods.Charles Taylor (1989) calls this the “buffered self,” protected from cosmic and communal claims.Its virtue lies in tolerance, its pathology in atomization.
Confucian ethics imagines the relationship as the moral unit.Responsibility flows both inward and outward in concentric circles—from filial piety to civic loyalty to cosmic harmony.Taylor’s “porous self,” open to the moral weight of others, better captures this worldview.The good person is not one who resists society but one who embodies it.As Mary Douglas (1970) might put it, the Chinese moral order treats pollution and disorder as equivalent: to violate harmony is to violate morality itself.
These competing anthropologies produce divergent expectations of government.Liberal citizens demand rights that restrain; Confucian citizens expect virtue that guides. When these expectations encounter each other—say, in global debates over Xinjiang or pandemic lockdowns—communication falters because each side appeals to incompatible moral grammars.
8.5 Justice and the moral economy of redistribution
Michael Walzer’s (1983) notion of “spheres of justice” helps clarify the difference in distributive ethics.In the liberal sphere, redistribution corrects inequality through abstract fairness; it is procedural and depersonalized.In the Confucian sphere, redistribution fulfills relational duty; it is expressive and moralized.China’s counterpart assistance (duìkǒu zhīyuán) redistributes not simply wealth but empathy—binding the rich province to the poor county in a relationship resembling kinship rather than contract.
Amartya Sen (1999) would define this as the enhancement of capabilities, yet China defines capability as participation in an ordered whole.Where Sen sees development as the freedom to choose, China sees it as the freedom to belong.This divergence explains why “labor-transfer poverty alleviation” can simultaneously appear as empowerment within China’s narrative and as coercion within Western discourse: both readings are internally consistent within their moral economies.
8.6 Power, virtue, and the paradox of moral authority
The ultimate tension between the two systems lies in their handling of the paradox of moral authority.If power claims moral purpose, how can it remain accountable?Liberalism answers by separating them; Confucianism answers by cultivating them.
In liberal regimes, corruption is a failure of law; in Confucian regimes, it is a failure of virtue.Hence anti-corruption campaigns in China are framed not merely as legal purges but as moral rejuvenations—an echo of the dynastic rectification of names (zheng ming).The state must constantly re-moralize itself to retain legitimacy.This cyclical purification, however, risks moral exhaustion: when every policy becomes virtue, dissent becomes sin.
Conversely, liberal states face moral anemia: when politics becomes purely procedural, citizens disengage.Alexis de Tocqueville already sensed this paradox in 1835 when he warned that democratic equality might breed apathy rather than virtue.Both systems thus struggle with the same problem from opposite directions—how to keep morality alive without letting it consume freedom.
8.7 Toward a dialogical understanding
Recognizing these contrasts does not demand moral relativism but moral bilingualism.Each system encodes a legitimate anxiety: the West’s fear of power without conscience, and China’s fear of conscience without order.If comparative politics is to move beyond caricature, it must read these fears as complementary insights rather than mutual indictments.
The liberal world could learn from China’s insistence that compassion can be organized; China could learn from liberalism’s insistence that compassion must not silence choice.In both traditions, the ideal polity is the one that reconciles care with autonomy—whether through law or through virtue.
Seen through this lens, China’s duìkǒu zhīyuán is not an anachronism but an experiment in moral engineering: an attempt to turn empathy into a public utility.It represents the persistence of a civilizational wager—that harmony, if properly cultivated, can be more humane than competition.
The juxtaposition does not privilege one over the other; it clarifies that what each calls “good governance” arises from different moral physics.Liberal governance seeks equilibrium through friction; Confucian governance seeks harmony through resonance.One disciplines virtue by suspicion, the other disciplines power by virtue.
Historical AnxietyMoral PrincipleInstitutional ReflexPolitical RiskThe West (Absolutism)Freedom as safeguard against virtue’s abuseSeparation of powers; rule of lawCynicism, moral vacuumChina (Disunity)Unity as condition for compassionMoralization of hierarchy; bureaucratic empathyConformism, moral overreach
Understanding these twin logics allows us to read China’s counterpart assistance neither as authoritarian spectacle nor as moral ideal, but as a historically intelligible synthesis: the governance of empathy in a civilization that equates order with care.
9 Conclusion: Counterpart Assistance as Moral Technology
China’s duìkǒu zhīyuán system stands as one of the most revealing experiments in what might be called moral technology—the translation of ethical traditions into administrative machinery. It fuses emotion and organization, Confucian benevolence and Weberian bureaucracy, producing a political form that unsettles familiar Western oppositions between state and society, coercion and consent, structure and sentiment. In this system, governance does not simply manage the population; it performs the virtue of care. The state assumes the moral posture of a family elder, coordinating empathy across vast distances and differences. Its moral vocabulary—ren (benevolence), yi (righteousness), he (harmony)—is made legible through fiscal transfers, cadre assignments, and cross-regional partnerships. Thus the paired assistance between provinces and counties, doctors and patients, cadres and villagers becomes a choreography of virtue at national scale.
The moral coherence of this architecture gives it enormous mobilizing power. When compassion is bureaucratically structured, empathy becomes reproducible; citizens see themselves not as instruments of policy but as participants in a shared moral enterprise. This emotional logic helps explain how large-scale campaigns, from Wenchuan reconstruction to pandemic control, could unfold with such speed and minimal visible coercion. The state’s legitimacy rests not only on performance but on affect—its capacity to elicit belonging through moral resonance. In moments of crisis, duìkǒu zhīyuán transforms the cold mechanics of administration into a theatre of collective empathy, demonstrating that efficiency in China often wears an ethical face.
Yet moral technology is never morally innocent. When benevolence becomes systematized, it risks hardening into orthodoxy. The very coherence that empowers duìkǒu zhīyuán can also produce moral absolutism: participation becomes duty, duty becomes virtue, and dissent becomes moral deviance. In this sense, the Confucian fusion of power and virtue carries within it the possibility of sanctifying authority. What appears to outsiders as coercion is, internally, experienced as care; what feels to participants like harmony may look from abroad like conformity. This tension is not a matter of misinformation but of moral translation—two civilizations organizing empathy through incompatible grammars of freedom and duty.
To understand duìkǒu zhīyuán therefore requires translation rather than endorsement. Comparative inquiry should neither romanticize China’s moralized governance nor condemn it by liberal criteria alone. It must ask how different political cultures embed morality within power: how Europe built freedom from distrust, and how China built trust from unity; how one guards against virtue’s excess while the other guards against its absence. Only through such cross-cultural literacy can scholars recognize that ethical governance is not a universal formula but a family of moral experiments, each answering the same human question in its own idiom—how authority can care without crushing, and how empathy can be scaled without losing its soul.
Duìkǒu zhīyuán, viewed in this light, is neither a relic of collectivist past nor a mere instrument of control. It is the living expression of a civilization that continues to believe that the state can, and must, feel. Its enduring challenge will be to sustain compassion without compulsion—to preserve the warmth of virtue in the machinery of power.
As the Book of Documents declares: “Harmonize the many states so that the people may live in peace.”
In contemporary China, that harmony takes bureaucratic form—an ancient empathy rendered as modern coordination.
References
Anderson, Benedict. 1983. Imagined Communities. London: Verso.
Asad, Talal. 2003. Formations of the Secular. Stanford University Press.
Bell, Daniel A. 2006. Beyond Liberal Democracy. Princeton University Press.
Brookings Institution. 2021. Aid and Development in Xinjiang. Washington DC.
Das, Veena, and Deborah Poole, eds. 2004. Anthropology in the Margins of the State. Oxford University Press.
Douglas, Mary. 1970. Natural Symbols: Explorations in Cosmology. London: Barrie and Rockliff.
Eisenstadt, S. N. 2000. “Multiple Modernities.” Daedalus 129 (1): 1–29.
Ferguson, James, and Akhil Gupta. 2002. “Spatializing States.” American Ethnologist 29 (4): 981–1002.
Fei, Xiaotong. 1947. From the Soil. Peking University Press.
GFDRR (World Bank). 2010. Wenchuan Earthquake Recovery. Washington DC.
Geertz, Clifford. 1973. The Interpretation of Cultures. Basic Books.
Hale, Thomas et al. 2021. “Global Government Responses to COVID-19.” Nature Human Behaviour 5: 529–538.
Huang, Yanzhong. 2020. “China’s COVID-19 Policy and the Strong State.” CFR Brief.
Lu, Xiaoli. 2021. “Administrative Mechanisms of Post-Disaster Reconstruction in China.” Disasters 45 (4): 781–803.
MacIntyre, Alasdair. 1981. After Virtue. Notre Dame University Press.
Mertha, Andrew. 2008. China’s Water Warriors. Cornell University Press.
Peng, L., and J. Liu. 2022. “Counterpart Assistance and Post-Disaster Economic Recovery.” Journal of Asian Economics 79: 101475.
Scott, James C. 1998. Seeing Like a State. Yale University Press.
Sen, Amartya. 1999. Development as Freedom. Oxford University Press.
Taylor, Charles. 1989. Sources of the Self. Harvard University Press.
Teets, Jessica C. 2014. Civil Society Under Authoritarianism. Cambridge University Press.
Tu, Weiming. 2010. Confucian Traditions in East Asian Modernity. Harvard University Press.
Walzer, Michael. 1983. Spheres of Justice. Basic Books.
Xu, Hua. 2019. “Government Behavior in Post-Disaster Housing Reconstruction.” Habitat International 84: 21–33.
Yan, Yunxiang. 2019. The Individualization of Chinese Society Revisited. Routledge.
Zhang, Xuefei. 2020. “China’s Whole-of-Nation Approach in Public Health Emergencies.” Center for Global Development Policy Paper.